What should a
medical doctor treating a person who refuses a blood transfusion on religious
grounds do if he feels the transfusion will save the patient’s life? Does
religious freedom extend to rejection of life-saving medical intervention? The
recent case of Kachasu (Suing as the Administrator of the Estate of the late Paul Kachasu) v Manda (Sued as Administrator
of the Estate of the late Dr Francis Manda) and Others (Appeal No.163 of 2021)
[2023] ZMCA 200 (30 August 2023) determined by the Court of Appeal dealt
with these questions.
The case involved
an 81-year-old prostate cancer patient, Paul Kachasu, who had expressly refused
a blood transfusion due to religious beliefs as a Jehovah’s Witness. Kachasu
had a Durable Power of Attorney of Health Care (DPA) expressing his refusal to
blood transfusion unless non-blood alternatives were deemed appropriate by his
treating physician. A DPA is a legal document that allows another person to
make healthcare decisions on the patient’s behalf in situations where they cannot
do so personally.
Despite this
directive, the doctor treating him gave Kachasu a blood transfusion while
unconscious in a bid to save his life. This action went directly against
Kachasu's expressed wishes and directives documented in the DPA. Unfortunately,
following the unauthorized blood transfusion, Kachasu passed away.
Following this event, the administrator of Kachasu's estate filed a lawsuit in the High Court, alleging assault and battery against the hospital and the physician who transfused him without consent. The High Court dismissed the case for want of jurisdiction. It held that the matter should have been brought as a constitutional claim by way of petition regarding the breach of fundamental rights and freedoms and not as a civil matter for battery and assault.
Dissatisfied with the Judgment, the Appellant appealed to the Court of Appeal, insisting that she had proceeded correctly before the High Court. The Court of Appeal decided in favour of the Appellant by holding that the administration of the blood transfusion against Kachasu's express refusal amounted to trespass to the person and was specifically battery, infringing upon Kachasu's right over his own body.
This article
argues that the holding of the Court of Appeal in this matter is correct and is
consistent with human rights standards. Although the Court of Appeal considered
the matter dispositive on the common law tort of assault or trespass to the
person, it highly relied on constitutional rights to arrive at the decision.
The Court noted that the Constitution enshrines liberty and religious freedom
as fundamental human rights. According
to the Court, the combined effect of these rights is to entitle a patient to
the principle of autonomy. This entails that an adult of full capacity could
refuse a blood transfusion, even if it was medically in his interest. In the
words of the Court, “All patients have the constitutional right to determine
what shall or shall not be done to them.” This, according to the Court, is what
constituted individual self-determination.
To appreciate the significance and correctness of the decision of the Court, it is important to understand the nature and significance of religious freedom in a democratic society. For believers, religion is the prism through which life is experienced, events are interpreted and given meaning. This was accurately stated in the case of Minister of Home Affairs and Another v Fourie and Another (CCT 60/04) [2005] ZACC (3): “For many believers, their relationship with God or creation is central to all their activities. It concerns their capacity to relate in an intensely meaningful fashion to their sense of themselves, their community and their universe. For millions in all walks of life, religion provides support and nurture and a framework for individual and social stability and growth. Religious belief can awaken concepts of self-worth and human dignity which form the cornerstone of human rights. Such belief affects the believer’s view of society and finds a distinction between right and wrong. It expresses itself in the affirmation and continuity of powerful traditions and frequently has an ancient character transcending historical epochs and national boundaries. For believers, then, what is at stake is not merely a question of convenience or comfort, but an intensely held sense about what constitutes the good and proper life and their place in creation.”
Considering the
diversity of religions and incongruence of beliefs, freedom of religion and
conscience invariably entails tolerance and accommodation of diversity. No
religion should assume a controlling role. As Professors De Vos and Freedman
have argued, it calls for the accommodation of “different and often
diametrically opposed beliefs and views about the world while respecting and
accommodating these diverse beliefs and views.”
The fact that some
beliefs are bizarre, illogical or inconsistent with the views of the majority
in society is not a sufficient basis to limit those rights. Diversity entails that believer should not be
put to the test of their beliefs in order to enjoy freedom of religion and
conscience. Religious freedom cannot just be enjoyed on the terms of the
majority or to the extent that the beliefs meet wide approbation in society. Was
it to be the case, that it would not be a right but a privilege? As Justice
Albie Sachs asserted: “The test for tolerance as envisaged by the Bill of
Rights comes not in accepting what is familiar and easily accommodated, but in
giving reasonable space to what is unusual, bizarre or even threatening.”
In other words, a
democratic society recognising freedom of religion and conscience should
accommodate even diametrically opposed beliefs and lifestyles. This, however,
does not mean believers are free to ‘do’ whatever they please. While believers
are free to ‘believe’ whatever they wish, considering that there are other
human beings with a host of rights and entitlements, believers cannot carry out
their beliefs into effect at any const. Respecting diversity and peaceful
co-existence requires respecting the rights of others as well. As the African
Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights held in the case of Prince v South Africa (2004) AHRLR 105 (ACHPR 2004): “Although the freedom to manifest
one's religion or belief cannot be realised if legal restrictions are
preventing a person from performing actions dictated by his or her convictions,
it should be noted that such freedom does not in itself include a general right
of the individual to act in accordance with his or her belief. While the right
to hold religious beliefs should be absolute, the right to act on those beliefs
should not. As such, the right to practice one's religion must yield to the
interests of society in some circumstances.”
The threshold, however, for restricting religious freedom is
high. As long as the membership of a religion is voluntary members are free to
leave if not content and religious views are not foisted upon them, then each
religion should be left alone to police its membership and determine its goals
and beliefs. Members of such religions are free to practice their faith and
manifest it, even to the point of self-destruction, as in the present case. The
only limit is when the expression of faith causes harm to others beyond mere
sensibilities. This was recognised by the European Court of Human Rights in the
case of Kokkinakis
v Greece 1993 Ser A No. 260-A where it was held that:
“The only limits on the exercise of this right are those dictated by respect
for the rights of others where there is an attempt to coerce the person into
consenting or to use manipulative techniques.”
The Court of
Appeal, therefore, made the correct decision in the present case. The decision
is not only sound at common law but is consistent with human rights standards. But,
if, in furtherance of a religious belief a person of sound mind and competence refuses
life-saving medical intervention, the state has no business forcing its goodwill
against such a believer. It does not matter that a life would be lost.
ABOUT THE AUTHORS
Dr. O’Brien Kaaba teaches law at the University of Zambia and is a Senior Research Fellow at Southern African Institute for Policy and Research (SAIPAR)
Hope Sthembile Homela is a legal Intern at Southern African Institute for Policy and Research (SAIPAR)